Tuesday, April 14, 2015

On Reflexivity in Anthropology 2008

On Reflexivity in Anthropology
Christopher Turner
Anthropology 500D
Spring 2008
written for a seminar under Jonathan Hill at SIU Carbondale

Abstract

            With the revamping and critical reevaluation of anthropology during the postmodernist movement of the late twentieth century, reflexivity became one of the tools by which members of the discipline sought to override their own observational biases encountered while conducting and constructing ethnographies. While it is impossible for the human observer locked within the human mind to gain a critical evaluative gaze that is completely free of an ingrained value laden perspective, reflexivity provides a method whereby the individual can to some extent situate and comprehend their own enculturated cognitive framework. Though reflexivity has loaned its interpretive schema to virtually every academic discipline imaginable, and while within anthropology it has come to take on a variety of differing definitions, the model and premise of the inwardly turned critical gaze is at the core of the solutions that have been adopted by the social sciences in response to the epistemological criticisms that have been leveled by the champions of the postmodernist paradigm.

                              [keywords: reflexivity, counter-transference, intersubjectivity]

Introduction  

            I have chosen to write about a topic that is incredibly broad, which consequently as subject matter has advantages and disadvantages. On a good note, there is a wide range of published  material on which to base investigations. The same is its disadvantage. A clear and developed comment and analysis on reflexivity could span several full length books, or could be the theme of numerous dissertations.
            Enter the term “reflexivity” in Google, and returned are seventy-three 20 page entries of websites. A Boolean search of Morris Library listings for “reflexivity” + “reflexive” under “any word anywhere” returns 161 listings, while the entire I-Share Catalog yields 536 responses. These library entries span titles from as diverse subject matter as Business Ethics as Practice: Representation, Reflexivity, and Performance  to  Time Gives It Proof: Paradox in the Late Music of Beethoven
            In this regard, in such a comparatively short paper, I will be unable to explore fully the concept of reflexivity. My intention is to examine the classic definition of the concept, its development through the twentieth century primarily within sociology, moving then to its marked effects on the discipline of anthropology, and support and criticism of its use in our field. While reflexivity can be qualified within sociology, literature, or more generally so in communication, I will be focusing my attention on its applications in ethnography.  Lastly,  I will briefly relate information about its unheralded antecedents as pioneered in the works of the 19th century ethnographer Frank Hamilton Cushing.     

History of the Reflexivity Concept 

            While often championed as an edict of the postmodern turn in late 20th century social sciences, the principle of reflexivity has a deep and varied past to which anthropology is a rather recent newcomer.  The great 17th century English jurist Sir Matthew Hale (1609-1676) is cited as having called reflexivity “the turning of the untethered eye inward upon its own actions” (Webster's 2nd Unabridged 1956). Hence we find the idea of  human meaning creation and its recursive nature being contemplated in late pre-Enlightenment Great Britain.           
            Schooled at Oberlin and Harvard, a professor at the Universities of Michigan and later Chicago, George Herbert Mead was a prominent American sociologist of the early 20th century. Though he described reflexivity strictly within the realm of sociology, he must be given credit for development of the concept overall (Salzman 2002:807). Mead describes the component of the self he called the “me”, the part of us that learns to negotiate social reality through adaptive mutual interchange .
            Mead (1934:138) attributes the selfness of the me arising as  “...the individual experiences himself ...from the particular standpoints of other individual members of the same social group, or from the generalized standpoint of the social group as a whole to which he belongs.” The implications for ethnography should be obvious. For the anthropologist relocated within the matrix of another society, the accustomed established indexical norms of communication are no longer present. We are able to engage within our own society due to our de facto familiarity with it, such that we “assume the attitudes of the individuals involved in it [knowing] how they feel about the assumption of their attitudes”(Mead 1934:176). In this regard, our reflexively gained ability to communicate has become a hindrance to meaningful ethnographic accounting when we are situated among the cultural other.
            Also during the 1930s, a different Mead, anthropology's Margaret, was broaching the topic of psychoanalysis in fieldwork. She famously described various cultures as group expressions of personality, an attribute that had in the Freudian sense been intended to describe individuals. Mead and her contemporaries were strongly influenced by Freud, who died in 1939.
            Freud, in his work with psychiatric patients, coined the term transference to describe a  phenomenon he observed in his patients during psychoanalysis. Individuals would project identities of past authority figures onto the psychiatrist during treatment. This non-pathological event was useful for the analyst because it revealed to some extent the defenses of the patient. More importantly though for the point of the present study is the associated concept of counter-transference. This occurs when the psychoanalyst begins to project their own feelings toward the patient. As Freud became more aware of the pitfalls of counter-transference, he “recommended that every analyst undergo personal analysis as well as a periodic self reflexive examination” (Spiro 2006:525). Here we have the idea that during a dyadic dialectical interchange, the observer, in this case a psychiatrist, can never be fully free of bias or a paradigmatic situatedness. Only with some form of examination of the observer, in this case that they be psychoanalyzed, is it possible to obtain a self awareness that can ultimately result in an individual whose interpretive matrix is more fully contextualized. The extension of this idea to ethnography never became fully developed, and field work and its subsequent literary productions remained a sort of travelogue and listing of cultural traits, usually reported in the third person.
            Again discussing sociology, I must mention the work of Harold Garfinkel, the 91 year old Professor Emeritus at USC. I must briefly refer to concepts developed in his most noted text Studies in Ethnomethodology (1967). For those of us saturated in anthropology, ethnomethodology is not quite what it may sound like. Anthropologists have a specific normative lexicon and a set of acquired working definitions whereby all discourse engaged in our field is premised. The same can be said about quotidian prosaic knowledge and meaning as created and exchanged within a society among its members. If someone walks in and says “It is raining”, it is known from the context of the setting that the speaker means that a moderate amount of liquid precipitation is falling from the sky outside of the  very building wherein they speak. It is known that they do not mean “It is raining in Paris”, nor is it an analogy suggesting that someone is crying, and it can even  be surmised that it is doing more than drizzling, yet it is not pouring. When they add “So I took the bus”, this does not suggest that they stole a bus to arrive dry, or that they rode in a yellow school bus. We do not think twice when we hear “It is raining so I took the bus”.
            This immediacy of meaning arises, according to Garfinkel, from our inculcated understanding within our given society. Hence the “ethno” portion of ethnomethodology must be qualified for the anthropologist: it is not a reference to a foreign and distant other, rather it refers to any unique human group wherein meaning is continually created and sustained through negotiated discourse, of course including one's own societal milieu. Such meaning is indexical within the setting of each specific discourse event [It is raining here outside], and is situated and created within the normative dialogic history of that specific social group. Garfinkel explored the degree to which indexical assumptions are encoded in normal conversation and other dialogical exchanges (Garfinkel 1967:1-11, 35-75).
            Lastly within the realm of sociology, mention must be made of the work of Sir Anthony Giddens. Giddens has championed the concepts of agency and structuration.  He has suggested that individual action and societal structure presuppose one another and form a dialectic. Structuration is created and recreated in the repeated activities of daily life.  “Social systems are systems of social interaction, so that they involve the situated activities of human subjects, and exist syntagmatically in the flow of time” (Giddens 1979:66, 69). Giddens acknowledges the view of Garfinkel: that meaning in human life is recursively negotiated amongst members of a given society, and that the results of this reflexive dialog are encoded in language. The use of indexical words (and actions) employed in a given language become barriers to mutual comprehension between one's own society and members of alternative human societies (Giddens 1976: 22-26).

Bindings of Logical Positivism

            The Post Enlightenment paradigm of positivism has within anthropology found a long intellectual history, traceable through works of Comte, Spencer, Tylor, Durkheim, Malinowski, and Radcliffe-Brown, to the materialism of Rappaport.  Perhaps fueled by the so-called vulgar materialism of Rappaport and the notion in social sciences of Binfordian hypotheses testing, it was not until around 1970 that anthropologists began to question the underlying premise suffused within their discipline: that one human can consciously and intentionally objectify and interpret the cultural and cognitive milieu of another. 
            Roscoe (1995:494) surveyed the anthropological literature, finding that references to arguments challenging positivism increased in number around 1971. He found only four such citings in the 25 years prior to that date, with seventeen mentions of the term from 1971 to 1975 alone. While he argues for a kinship between hermeneutics and the scientific method, he acknowledges the chasm between their properties, particularly in the ethnographic case. The scientist can garner data from the world at large, which is omnipresent and accessible to all observers. An example of this as cited by Roscoe is that of astronomers taking spectrographs of stars: the objective reality of stars, uninfluenced by the observer, typifies the methodological distancing that is intrinsic to data collection employed in using the positivist paradigm and its minion, the scientific method. Conversely, the observational authority of the ethnographer is based on singular sets of data that are gathered while they are alone in the field, which setting is reproducible only with great expense and difficulty by others (Roscoe 1995:498). In this regard, post modern critics have run roughshod over ethnography in particular. They posit that its errors are the result of some greater epistemological flaw, but in so doing they overlook  that the limitations of any observational science which is restricted to a singular observer or authority, as is customarily the case with the ethnographic narrative, is also similarly limited (Salzman 2002:811). 
            As pointed out by Roscoe (1995), positivism as such has become an easy target for  postmodernists in all social sciences, but especially in ethnography. He suggests that such critics miss the point that constructed “fragments of discourse” can be neither more nor less  “true” than hypotheses generated by the scientific method. Roscoe (1995:497) argues that anthropologists  have espoused an  “overly mechanistic view of natural science that has obscured not only the thoroughly hermeneutic nature of science but also the thoroughly scientific nature of their own hermeneutic ethnography.”
            The atomistic nature of all events, whether molecular, macroscopic, cosmological, or regarding those which occur during dialogical intercourse amongst humans, prevents their full and complete description. The independence of all actions, and the infinitude of events which constitute all observable phenomenon, has been described by chaos theory, upon which I will not elaborate here. Suffice it to say that no generalizing laws are fully capable of describing in total the behavior of activities in any realm of the observable universe, whether in the natural sciences or in the humanities (Roscoe 1995:499-500). Criticisms of ethnography as being non-scientific and not accountable  to positivism are incorrect. Ethnographic accounts are just a particular case where the repeatability of the observations is restricted, and where the observing tools utilized lie primarily within the human mind itself. Reflexivity becomes the method whereby the observer can learn to reduce and situate, but never fully eliminate, their own inherent biases.

Reflexivity in Modern Anthropology

            With reference to reflexivity, a major work examining objectivity within ethnography came with George Devereux's From Anxiety to Method in the Behavioral Sciences (1967). Devereux was trained as both a psychoanalyst and as an anthropologist, giving him a greater insight into the meeting place of the two. While earlier sociologists had utilized the working notion of reflexivity, it had been restricted to its use within the context of meaning creation by and between  members of a given society. It was Freud's examination of such recursively enjoined dialog within the realm of psychiatry that had revealed the systematic errors inherent to the dyadic dialectic exchange that characterized both psychoanalysis and the ethnologist's paradigm. Devereux formally expounded upon the definition of reflexivity as regards the latter discipline. 
            The reexamination of the aloof detached observer and their presumptive objectivity had been in the offing across the sciences, both natural and social,  throughout the first half of the twentieth century.  Einstein's most well known contribution to physics was indeed called “The Theory of Relativity”.  He posited that the physical parameters marking the observer's situation-- e.g. location, velocity, and mass – effected the quantitative outcome of the experimental results. This was followed in the 1930s again in physics with the Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle. This maxim suggested that the observer's  very presence altered the physical properties of the event being observed and hence of the data so collected. Because such observational sciences were the fundament that founded the notion of impartiality within the scientific method,  the suggestion that such objectivity did not exist even within physics inevitably called the ostensibly subjective accounts of the social sciences into question (LaBarre 1967:vi-x).
            Devereux concisely described the conundrum entailed within the ethnographic event. He described the ontology of the putatively objective data collected in the behavioral sciences, particularly in ethnography,  as threefold in production:

  1. The behavior of the subject.
  2. The 'disturbances' produced by the existence and observational activities of the observer.
  3. The behavior of the observer: His[i] anxieties, his defensive maneuvers, his research strategies, his 'decisions' (= his attribution of a meaning to his observations)(from Devereux 1967:xix).

            In From Anxiety to Method, Devereux (1967:xviii) suggested that the notion of objectivity in  ethnography is an illusion, not due to the arguably subjective nature of the social sciences, but because positivism itself is a human philosophy, and not an independently extant quality of reality. The very notions of parsimony, compendiousness, and self-consistency are not necessarily inherent qualities of mind within the universe, but are really theories of interpretation (1967:11).  While the hallmarks of the cognitive, gestaltic, and psychoanalytic models were accepted as subjective and value-laden, the physicalistic and mathematical models of the hard sciences had thus far escaped such definition (1967:11, 29). The stultifying, concretizing eye of the descriptive ethnographer had been unintentionally reifying the other,  such that one so situated  “embalms seeds instead of planting them” (1967:30). Devereux's way out of this seemingly incontrovertible observational paradox was to employ the Freudian notion of counter-transference.
            The title of Devereux's book points toward the thrust of his commentary: it is the very anxiety that is aroused in the ethnographer that becomes their greatest avenue of insight into analyzing the nature and degree of their own inherent biases. Former day ethnographers, perhaps  most famously Malinowski, failed to address their own anxiety within the context of the ethnographic narrative, eventuating in Malinowski's case in the writing of a parallel document replete with its own pathology (Stocking 1983:71, 93-112). Devereux suggests that it is this very tension that serves as the window into the mind of the self-situated ethnographer. The ethnographer must accomplish the seemingly impossible task of seeing through the biases of their mind, while using their own mind.
            I found Devereux's accounts of such situational biases to be well explicated, but I was less satisfied with his mapping a way out of the implicit conundrum. Valerie Yow (1997:79) does a better job at articulating the methodology of self-examination that can liberate the ethnographer from this predicament:

“There  are  specific questions  to ask  so that  we understand  what is happening:
1.  What  am  I feeling about  this narrator [i.e. the subject under study]?
2.  What similarities and what differences impinge on this interpersonal situation?
3.  How does my own ideology affect this process? What group outside of the process am I identifying  with?
4.  Why am I  doing the  project in the first place?
5.  In selecting topics and questions, what alternatives might I have taken? Why didn't I choose these?
6.  What other possible interpretations are there? Why did I reject  them?
7.  What are the effects on me as I go about this research? How are my reactions impinging  on the  research?” 

            In this regard, the goal is not to eradicated subjectivity, which is impossible, but to acknowledge it and attempt to reduce and perspectivize it. As suggested by Roscoe (1995), all investigations involve judgments, and all contain elements of value laden truth concepts. The goal is not to escape positivism, a feat that cannot be accomplished without abandoning logic, but to use it to most aptly ameliorate biases. Just as the chemist or physicist gives their best effort at calibrating and zeroing their measuring devices: scales, calipers, thermometers; so too must the ethnographer calibrate their tools of scientific inquiry, in this case their actions, behaviors, inquisitions, and interpretative schemata.
            Some earlier ethnographers are credited with using the reflexive method to illustrate the inherent systemic flaws within an unbridled ethnography. Levi-Strauss produced Tristes Tropiques in 1955. The literary classic is in the dense style of European writing circa World War II. Its author pines for the romanticized pre-Industrial world, nobelizing not the prototypical savage but all of former day humanity, all that had not been despoiled by contact with Homo europicanus. While the account breaks with the mold of earlier static ethnographies, it is hardly a guidebook on how to renegotiate one's own observational biases. It is more so a straightforward introspective autobiographical travelogue, if I dare say so about the still-living master's work (for similar criticisms see Dumont 1978:10-11). Nonetheless, it is often cited in regards to early examples of reflexivity in ethnography.
            Another example from the same period is Laura Bohannan's 1954 novel Return to Laughter. Written under the pseudonym of Elenore Smith Bowen, the account is purely fictitious.[ii] It is invariably lauded in this regard and is cited as an example of reflexivity in action. The novel is set in Africa amongst the Tiv where Bohannan undertook actual real-world ethnography. I have not read the book, nor am I familiar with her ethnographic work. As such, it is unclear to me whether Bohannan was attempting to augment her research interpretations by portraying her subject from a distinctly different vantage point, and was hence aiming Return to Laughter at fellow anthropologists, or if in fact she was attempting to overtly produce a novel as based on her personal experiences that were gained through her efforts during her fieldwork.  It and Tristes Tropiques typify the genre called the confessional ethnography. While I lack the necessary background reading to confidently comment on this genre of ethnographies, I will go out on a limb and suggest that these do not appear to be teleologically driven to produce a more insightful accounting or interpretation of each author's ethnographic material[iii], and in this regard they are not manifesting and utilizing reflexivity as described by Devereux or Yow.
            In an article subtitled “The Emergence of Narrative Ethnography”, Barbara Tedlock  (1991) details the period from 1930 up to the 1980s, outlining the development and occurrences of  confessional or autobiographical ethnographies.  These span the gamut from Gladys Reichard's Spider Woman (1934) to Paul Rabinow's 1977 Reflections on Field Work in Morocco. As suggested by Tedlock, the key distinguishing trait of these accounts is their use of the first person pronoun. Citing Evans-Pritchard's The Nuer (1940), she notes that the author “...included a seven-page first-person  confessional account of the terrible living conditions and informant difficulties he experienced during  fieldwork in the Sudan. In sharp contrast, the remainder of the book, written in an omniscient third-person authoritative voice, describes highly abstract... actions...:  the Nuer  do  this,  the Nuer  do  that” (Tedlock 1991:74). The innovation suggested with Evans-Pritchard's introduction and subsequent confessional and auto-ethnography was the rescission of the putatively objectifying 3rd person literary device. It had been practically taboo amongst anthropologists to include the self within the ethnographic narrative. While intersubjectivity could be explored with a first person voice, such articulation was not tantamount to the use of reflexivity. The term reflexive appears only three times in Tedlock's article, once in text, once in a citation, and another time in a footnote. Tedlock does not equate the use of reflexivity with the change in person deixis.  In footnote 16, she briefly suggests a definition for reflexivity: “In ordinary  "reflectiveness",  one is conscious  of oneself  as an Other,  but  in "reflexivity,"  one is conscious  of being  self-conscious  of oneself  as an Other” (italics author's 1991:85). Here we get a serpentine, self-referential definition that hardly elucidates. While Tedlock's article is explanatory and well written with regard to the advent of the auto-ethnography, it is evident that such narratives do not implicitly employ reflexivity and its radical self-inspection. They merely expand the ethnographer's account to include the self in the observer-participant dyad. 
            During the 1970s and 1980s, numerous volumes and articles detailing reflexivity in anthropology appeared. It will be impossible for me to have read and reviewed let alone to mention all of these. I will instead concentrate on some key examples that are repeatedly cited in ethnographic literature.
            A good case of this is A Crack in the Mirror (1982), edited by Jay Ruby. This is a collection of essays treating the diversely interpreted notion of reflexivity. As is usual with treatises in the social sciences after the advent of postmodernism, proofs of argument are rooted less in the accumulation of acceptable premises, and seem instead to rely on clever twists of logic that may or may not withstand full elucidation. Dense writing and non-linear thinking is the norm in such constructs. It is as if one is commended on the abstruseness of an argument, rather than on its sensible delineation: after all, common sense and normative cognition are pilloried by the postmodernist.
            While A Crack in the Mirror does not espouse the full-blown relativity of postmodernism, it definitely privileges the perspective of the self. Starting on page one, reflexivity is channeled into the working definition of “consciousness about consciousness, thinking about thinking”. In the aftermath of Dadaism and the psychedelic era of the 1960s, the use of jarring imagery as a didactic tool became more acceptable, invoked as if to elicit the illumination of a Zen koan. Tellingly in this regard, Myerhoff and Ruby (1982:1-35) cite Frank Zappa, Marcel Duchamp, Tom Wolfe, Andy Warhol, Bob Dylan, Kurt Vonnegut, etc. The result is a flippant, shallow version of reflexivity. These authors never once mention George Devereux, Harold Garfinkel, nor Freud.  The version of reflexivity they espouse and proffer is much closer to the confessional autobiography than to the self-examination of methodology as suggested by Yow (1997). They boast of the increased use of the autobiography as a technique for inquiry. “We find recurring films about filmmakers, prints of printmakers making prints, photographs of photographers and their equipment, plays about playwrights”(Myerhoff and Ruby 1982:9). Like the verbose self-absorbed victim at a cocktail party who wears their problems on their sleeve rather than solving them, the Myerhoff /Ruby form of reflexivity would have the ethnographer air every iota of their internal discourse encountered in the field to the beleaguered ear of the reader. “The more the ethnographer attempts to fulfill a scientific obligation to report on methods, the more [they] must acknowledge that [their] own behavior and persona in the field are data”(1982:26).  One chapter in A Crack in the Mirror is entitled “How to Look at Us Looking at the Yanomami Looking at Us” (Michaels 1982:133-148)[iv]. The koan-like title exemplifies my point about the ill-defined, riddle-like nature of the book's arguments. The purpose of using reflexivity is to escape the confines (as much as is possible) of the biased eye of the observer. It is a self-reflective method that never need be explicated to the reader except indirectly inasmuch as it has altered the interpretations of the collected ethnographic data.  The methodological revisions offered by Myerhoff and Ruby are only extensions of the same unquestioned eye, whose field of view has simply been expanded to include more processes and data, in this case, a purported identification with the gaze of the other[v] : “The ethnographer becomes audience for a performance so that he or she can become a performer for us, the audience”(1982:30). This sort of “reflexivity” purports to acquire a less-fettered viewpoint by transposing its gaze through another observer and then back into the original judging gaze. These conundra remind me, to play their game, of Bob Dylan's line about  “the one who tries to hide what they don't know to begin with.”[vi]
            I am not alone with such criticism. Graham Watson (1987:29) wrote about his reaction to a conference held in 1984 on reflexivity:  “While listening to papers being presented there, it occurred to me that when anthropologists talk about reflexivity, either they do not know what they are talking about or they are talking about something other than what they seem to be talking about.” He suggested that speakers were “claiming to confront reflexivity while merely managing it”. Watson believes that some anthropologists cannot confront true reflexivity because it undermines their authority as narrators. By “managing” reflexivity, they keep themselves in the privileged role of controlling the situation and are never compelled to disengage from their predisposed methodologies (Watson 1987:33). Levi-Strauss (1955:385) put it well when he wrote “Since we are permanently unable to escape from the norms by which we have been conditioned, our attempt to put different societies, including our own into perspective are said to be no more than a shame faced way of admitting superiority over all others.” Championing what he sees as the most apt form of reflexivity, Watson (1987:34)  goes on to cite Hammersley and Atkinson's  Ethnography:  Principles in Practice (1983:236):  “...one of the distinguishing characteristics of science for us is precisely its reflexive self-consciousness about methodology [where] there is an obligation placed upon practitioners to scrutinize systematically the methodology by which findings, their own and others, are produced, and in particular to consider how the activities of the researcher may have shaped those findings.” The reader will notice how close in substance the statement is to that of Valerie Yow cited earlier.
            Another good example concerning the ambiguity and multi-valence of the reflexivity concept is revealed in the short essay by Ohnuki-Teirney (1984). The Japanese born anthropologist relates her experience of returning to Japan to undertake ethnography after having lived in the US for two decades. At first, though she was raised there, she was taken aback by the culture she encountered in Japan: “...they seemed strange, with intriguing behavioral patterns and thought processes” (1984:584). She notes having felt enlivened and stimulated by the foreignness of the Japanese in Kobe, whom she observed in her capacity as ethnologist. After some 6 weeks she reports that the newness had worn off and that she began to feel more like one of “them”, as she phrases it. In response, Ohnuki-Teirney returned to the US.   “...[A]fter  about four months I felt the need to pull back from them to regain a sense of reflexive perspective” (1984:584).  Here, we see an anthropologist interpreting the reflexive paradigm as if it is intended to create a distancing effect on the observer. Others would perhaps argue that it was precisely when she began to feel ingrained within the societal milieu of Kobe that she was best positioned to make incisive observations. To my thinking, reflexivity does not purport itself to be the remedy to the dichotomous relationship resulting from one's degree of nativeness or lack thereof. It is rather a method whereby we can learn to observe and contextualize our cognitive positionality, of which nativeness is just one dimension.  Ohnuki-Teirney's understanding of the “reflexive perspective” simply becomes a rehashing of the classic version of the objectified observer-participant viewpoint, a viewpoint which was premised on the notion of possessing an observational acuity deriving from the ethnographer's very foreignness. Reflexivity seeks to burst the bubble of such putative objectivity, and to turn the mind's eye to the self, thereby examining one's own cognitive framework, and to as skillfully as one can, negotiate inherent inevitable biases and inculcated interpretive schemata which we all possess.      

Cushing's Antecedent to Reflexivity

            As described earlier, the notion of reflexivity was long in developing, and even longer in entering ethnography. Yet 50 years prior to its discussion by George Herbert Mead in the late 1920s, a form of reflexivity was being practiced by the oft overlooked anthropological pioneer Frank Hamilton Cushing. Cushing was part of an expedition to the southwestern United States funded by the Smithsonian Institution in the late 1870s, spending four years with the Zuni people from 1879 to 1882. His ethnographic accomplishments are invariably overlooked in anthropology today. For instance, he proceeded Malinowski by forty years in employing the participant-observer method during his stay with the Zuni[vii] (Hinsley 1983:56-58, Mark 1980). Of note here however with regard to reflexivity is what Cushing called the reciprocal method. Rather than only absorbing didactically the culture of the other, Cushing and the Zuni would trade stories. “Folklore and myths were not collected but rather exchanged” (Mark1980:103). He wrote that “...my method must succeed, I live among the Indians, I eat their food, and sleep in their houses. [...I] will look with unfeigned reverence on their beautiful and ancient ceremonies, never laughing at any absurd observance, they love me, and I learn” (Green 1990:60). Cushing would give informal classes in history and philosophy, underscoring his notion of exchange within what he called the reciprocal method (Green 1990:167).  While this form of reflexivity is closer in tone to the sort of dialectical interchange (Page 1997) outlined by Ruby than to that of Devereux, it is nonetheless recursive in approach and was a century ahead of its time. [viii]
             Cushing's perception of language as a barrier to understanding the Zuni had compelled him to strive to master their native tongue. Yet as an ethnographer, Cushing shunned the dry typological accounting of cultural features. Resultantly, when producing ethnographic narratives, writing in English, he freely translated Zuni folk tales with the nuances of his own language that he felt to be appropriate in capturing the meaning he encountered in the field. He has been roundly criticized for such methods as being a form of embellishment and falsification (Tedlock 1983:33-36). Critics of Cushing adhere to the static literal mode of cross-cultural representation, not recognizing that it is inevitably impossible to capture the subtleties of such an exotic foreign language as Zuni. While Cushing's English translations from the late 1800s of Zuni folktales may sound flowery today to the modern ear, his accounts have a distinctly human tone to them commensurate with the storytelling genre. This is especially so when compared to the analytical efforts of works such as those by Tedlock (1983) that are suffused with diacritic marks and presented in schematically choreographed  paragraphs, denuded of all sense of humanity and the natural flow of the spoken word .
            Cushing seemed to grasp in the reflexive sense that it is the entire human mind that must be employed in interpreting and representing the ethnographic account of another culture, not just a verbatim dry dehumanizing replication of the purported facts. Being a human in the midst of humans, he enjoined his humanity in the portrayal of humanity. If such methodology had been more keenly observed within anthropology on a continuing basis, the need for the postmodern revolt may well have been lessened or even vitiated, or perhaps, exacerbated further.

Comments and Personal Observations on Reflexivity

            With the realization that true objectivity is never attainable, reflexivity becomes the portal through which we can see our own misshapen parochial world views. These are produced by both our societal inculcation, and by the vagaries of our own human foibles and personal experiences. It is easy to imagine that certain individuals of particular personality types would not make successful ethnographers. Those with strongly focused wills, individuals who need to perceive reality with the caveat that they are in control at all times, would perhaps be unable to disengage with the self to the degree necessary to enjoin the self-reflexive inspection. The ethnographer must allow for a measured loss of identity necessary for the detached perspective needed to de-situate their own comfort zone, while still retaining an eye for recording behavioral detail. 
            The reflexive conundrum finds its greatest paradox embodied in the social science interview. In normal dyadic discourse in quotidian interactions, reflexivity is not a problem, in fact, following Giddens' idea of structuration, it is the glue which holds the encounter together and the seed which makes the dialogical interchange within the context of society the wellspring for the creation of culture. Atoms of personal agency that foment and arise within the grainless continuum of living dialog are the symbionts of reflexivity.  It is when the ethnographer intrudes into a social situation with the premise of gathering data and observing society that the problematic nature of such discourse comes to the fore.
             The classic model of ethnographic interaction is that the anthropologist intentionally relocates to a distant culture expressly to negotiate the otherness and to distill therefrom an account of a human society in action. This immediately creates a language barrier that ethnology has long confronted, and which it is ostensibly able to overcome by mastery of the different code we call a foreign language. Of course, we can never learn all of the intricacies of the associated meta-code. Also, the anthropologist is expected to legitimatize their study by remaining as long as is practically possible with the distant other, for months or better yet years, so as to have time to penetrate to the true depths of the very nature of the society or group being studied. It is exactly under such circumstances that the anxiety explicated by Devereux most intensely comes to the fore. Ethnographers have become contemptuous of their subjects (itself a semantically charged word), as with Malinowski, or have overly identified with them and had to negotiate feelings of love, emotional involvement, or the temptation to go native, a charge with which Cushing is still branded today (Tedlock 1991).



Conclusions

            Reflexivity in one form or another has been around for hundreds of years. It found its greatest development throughout the first half of the twentieth century within the discipline of sociology, while well constructed notions that paralleled reflexivity arose within the practice of Freudian psychoanalysis. Freud's concept of counter-transference is the bedrock upon which later efforts by George Devereux were founded. He gave what I consider to be the fullest substance to the working definition of reflexivity. Using Freud's principle of counter-transference, Devereux reasoned that the anxiety experienced by the ethnographer became the best window into the usually veiled internal dialog of the mind of the field worker. Like the proverbial idea of pulling one's self up by one's own bootstraps, it is nearly an impossibility to engage with and disarm inherent biases successfully. Reflexivity becomes the method whereby an observer can gain some insight into the perspective of their own ethnographic gaze. This is achieved, as Sir Mathew Hale's definition from the seventeenth century suggests, by “the turning of the untethered eye inward upon its own actions.”  As outlined by Valerie Yow, the observer must take an incisive inventory of their own reasonings and viewpoints. Becoming mentally agitated in the field, Devereux's anxiety, allows particular interstices within the flow of the ethnographer's internal dialog to be used to gain insight into the cultural differences between the observer and the observed, and to see more clearly the predisposed intellectual framework of the anthropologist. A paced thoughtful introspection of the cognitive milieu of the individual can allow the field worker to regain a mental equilibrium and assist in coming to terms with their observational viewpoint.  This is much like the effect gained with  psychiatrists being themselves psychoanalyzed, as Freud recommended. While we can never become completely free of value laden judgments, it is the best we can do to calibrate our own cognitive situatedness.
            This method is not the same as that employed by anthropologists throughout part of the twentieth century that was obtained by writing auto-ethnographies. While these literary forms perhaps are an improvement over those versed strictly in a third person format, they do not involve reflexivity as such. Reflexivity has perhaps been misunderstood by ethnographers writing confessional narratives, if in so doing they were trying implicitly to regauge their inherent viewpoint. It can be argued that the auto-ethnographic approach does little more than expand an already limited critical gaze. Simply enjoining with a first person deixis does not guarantee the removedness necessary to surmount a myopic view that can be at least partially ameliorated by a reflexive self-accounting.  
            Though there may be some ambiguity as to exactly what constitutes the reflexive act, it would be improper to say that anthropologists of all stripes have completely misunderstood the idea. The use of reflexivity spans a wide range of academic categories, and even within anthropology itself has so many different working definitions, that though they may be in conflict with each other, it seems that reflexivity legitimately represents a variety of concepts to a variety of individuals. Any increased degree of self-inspection resulting from any of these variants constitutes an improvement on a static reified viewpoint. 












References Cited

Bowen, Elenore Smith
            1954    Return to Laughter. New York: Harper Brothers
Cushing. Frank H.
            1892    Manual Concepts: a Study of the Influence of Hand Usage on Culture Growth.                                 American Anthropologist 5:273-276.
            1895    Primitive Copper Working: an Experimental Study. American Anthropologist 7:93-117.
Devereux, George
            1967    From Anxiety to Method in the Behavioral Sciences. Paris: Mouton and Company.
Dumont, Jean-Paul
            1978    The Headman and I: Ambiguity and Ambivalence in the Fieldworking Experience.                            Austin: University of Texas Press.
            1986    Prologue to Ethnography or Prolegomena to Anthropography. Ethos 14(4):344-367.
Evans-Pritchard, Edward Evan
            1940    The Nuer, a Description of the Modes of Livelihood and Political Institutions of a                              Nilotic People. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Garfinkel, Harold
            1967    Studies in Ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Giddens, Anthony
            1976    New Rules of Sociological Method: a Positive Critique of Interpretive Sociologies.                            Stanford: Stanford University Press. 
            1979    Central Problems in Social Theory: Action, Structure, and Contradiction in Social                 Analysis. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Green, Jesse
            1990    Cushing at Zuni: the Correspondence and Journals of Frank Hamilton Cushing, 1879-                       1884. Albuquerque: University of New Mexico Press.
Hammersley,  Martyn  and  Paul Atkinson 
            1983    Ethnography:  Principles  in Practice.  London:  Tavistock.
Hinsley, Curtis M.
            1983    Ethnographic Charisma and Scientific Routine: Cushing and Fewkes in the American                        Southwest, 1879-1893. In Observers Observed: Essays on Ethnographic Fieldwork.                                      George F. Stocking, ed. Pp. 53-69. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
LaBarre, Weston
            1967    Preface. In From Anxiety to Method in the Behavioral Sciences by George Devereux.                       Pp. vi-x. Paris: Mouton and Company.
Levi-Strauss, Claude
            1955    Tristes Tropiques. English translation by John and Doreen Weightman (1974). New                            York: Atheneum.
Mark, Joan
            1980    Four Anthropologists: an American Science in the Early Years. New York: Neale                    Watson Academic Publishing.
Mead, George Herbert
            1934    Mind, Self, and Society from the Standpoint of a Social Behaviorist. Chicago:                                   University of Chicago Press.
Michaels, Eric
            1982    How to Look at Us Looking at the Yanomami Looking at Us. In A Crack in the Mirror:                     Reflexive Perspectives in Anthropology. Edited by Jay Ruby. Pp. 133-147. Philadelphia:                   University of Pennsylvania.             
Myerhoff, Barbara and Jay Ruby
            1982    Introduction. In A Crack in the Mirror: Reflexive Perspectives in Anthropology.     Edited                              by Jay Ruby. Pp. 1-35. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania. 
Ohnuki-Tierney, Emiko
            1984    "Native" Anthropologists. American Ethnologist 11(3):584-586.
Page, Miriam Dempsey
            1997    Clifford Geertz and Beyond: the Interpretive Interview/Essay and Reflexive                                     Ethnography. Paper presented at the 48th Annual Conference on College Composition and                            Communication. Phoenix, AZ.  Accessed online March 2008 http://www.eric.ed.gov/ERIC                           WebPortal/custom/portlets/recordDetails/detailmini.jsp?_nfpb=true&_&ERICExtSearch_                SearchValue_0=ED408618&ERICExtSearch_SearchType_0=no&accno=ED408618                    
Rabinow, Paul
            1977    Reflections on Fieldwork in Morocco. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Reichard, Gladys A.
            1934    Spider Woman; a Story of Navajo Weavers and Chanters. New York: Macmillan.
Roscoe, Paul B.
            1995    The Perils of 'Positivism' in Cultural Anthropology. American Anthropologist 97(3):492-        504.
Ruby, Jay
            1982    A Crack in the Mirror: Reflexive Perspectives in Anthropology. Philadelphia: University        of Pennsylvania. 
Salzman, Philip Carl
            2002    On Reflexivity. American Anthropologist 104(3):805-813.
Spiro, Melford E.
            2006    Postmodernist Anthropology, Subjectivists, and Science: a Modernist Critique. In                 Anthropology in Theory: Issues in Epistemology. Henrietta L. Moore, Todd Sanders, eds. Pp.           523-536. Malden Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishing.
Stocking, George W.
            1983    The Ethnographer's Magic: Fieldwork in British Anthropology from Tylor to                                      Malinowski. In Observer's Observed: Essays on Ethnographic Fieldwork. George W.                                     Stocking. Editor. Pp. 70-120. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
Tedlock, Barbara
            1991    From Participant Observation to the Observation of Participation: The Emergence of
               Narrative Ethnography. Journal of Anthropological Research 47(1):69-94.
Tedlock, Dennis
            1983    The Spoken Word and the Work of Interpretation. Philadelphia: University of                                    Pennsylvania.
Watson, Graham
            1987    Make Me Reflexive, but Not Yet: Strategies for Managing Essential Reflexivity in
                Ethnographic Discourse. Journal of Anthropological Research 43(1):29-41.
Websters 2nd Unabridged Dictionary
            1956    Springfield, Massachusetts: GNC Merriam.
Yow, Valerie
            1997    "Do I like Them Too Much?": Effects of the Oral History Interview on the Interviewer                       and Vice-Versa. The Oral History Review 24(1):55-79.





[i]     Devereux wrote before the advent of gender issues in anthropology and uses the masculine “he” throughout.
[ii]    It is perhaps insightful to note that the academic body of ethnographers and anthropologists would praise the fictional Return to Laughter for its innovative form and purported usage of reflexivity, while the same cadre of commentators defame and deride ostensible works of fiction by Carlos Castaneda. The latter never acknowledged the fictitious nature of his series of books based on his ethnographic involvement with the Yaqui Indian Don Matus in Mexico. Matus was a practitioner of the use of psychotropic plants, and the accounts rendered by Castaneda include illogical states of mind induced by the hallucinogens administered to him by the Yaqui curendaro. Matus described entire versions of reality that are at odds with normative non-pathological awareness. Yet Castaneda's accounts have never been praised for examining non-normal shamanic modes of cognition and understanding, nor for their insight into questioning the relativistic nature of an objectified interpretation of reality.
[iii]   Jean-Paul Dumont wrote in The Headman and I: “I emphatically do not intend to dwell myopically on...the self-indulgent emotions of a fieldworker mainly attempting, by confessional narratives, to create an introspective travelogue...”(1978:3).
[iv]   Michaels' article is neither primarily about the Yanomami, nor does it overtly discuss the theoretical implications of reflexivity. It is rather a look at the increasing use of film in portraying the ethnographic moment and message.
[v]    “While  we  already  know  all  too  well  the  problems  that  an "objective"  anthropology  entails,  it  appears  now  that  an  anthropology  of the"subject"  might  not  be quite  viable  either...” (Dumont 1986:358).
[vi]   From Bob Dylan's song Positively 4th Street (1965).
[vii]  Not only was Cushing a pioneer with the observer-participant method, but he also accomplished many other “firsts” for which he has not been credited. He preceded Boas in speaking of culture in the relativistic sense as early as 1882 (Mark 1980:109-112, Green 1990:356). Also foreshadowing Boas, Cushing practiced the four-fold approach to anthropology while in the field with the Zuni (Green 1990:99-107). He practiced recreating chert reduction methods and copper tool fabrication, now called chaine operatoire or operational sequence studies (Cushing 1892, 1895).  Cushing also as early as the late 1880s led a multi-disciplinary team to explore archaeological sites in Arizona (Hinsley 1983:60), an achievement often credited as first pioneered by A.V. Kidder's work at Pecos pueblo circa 1920.
[viii]         In keeping with the reflexive introspection as outlined with Devereux, I must acknowledge my own identification with Cushing as underdog. I myself have been plagiarized and blacklisted  by members of the anthropologic academic community, and have had scholastic grades influenced by such prevailing prejudices. I have had works of mine ignored by such entities. As such, not only can I relate to what has happened to Cushing's work, but I am likely to over interpret affronts toward his written corpus in this regard.

No comments:

Post a Comment